Difference between revisions of "Exercises:Mond - Topology - 1"

From Maths
Jump to: navigation, search
(Created page with "__TOC__ ==Section A== ==Section B== Exercises 6, 7 and 8 make use of the compact-to-Hausdorff theorem ===Question 6=== {{/Question 6}} ==Section C== ==Notes== <references...")
 
m
Line 5: Line 5:
 
===Question 6===
 
===Question 6===
 
{{/Question 6}}
 
{{/Question 6}}
 +
===Question 7===
 +
{{/Question 7}}
 
==Section C==
 
==Section C==
 
==Notes==
 
==Notes==

Revision as of 11:31, 8 October 2016

Section A

Section B

Exercises 6, 7 and 8 make use of the compact-to-Hausdorff theorem

Question 6

Part I

Find a surjective continuous mapping from [1,1]R to the unit circle, S1 such that it is injective except for that it sends 1 and 1 to the same point in S1. Definitions may be explicit or use a picture

Solution
Take -1 to any point on the circle (we pick the south pole in this diagram), then go around the circle clockwise at a constant speed such that by f(1) one has done a full revolution and is back at the starting point.

The right-hand-side is intended to demonstrate that the interval (1,1) to the circle without the south-pole is bijective, ie it is injective and surjective, so the diagram on the left is "almost injective" in that it is injective everywhere except that it maps 1 and 1 both to the south pole.
As required
We shall define f:[1,1]S1 to be such a map:
  • f:t(sin(π(t+1))cos(π(t+1))), this starts at the point (1,0) and goes anticlockwise around the circle of unit radius once.
    • Note: I am not asked to show this is continuous, merely exhibit it.
    • Note: The reason for the odd choice of sin for the x coordinate, and the minus signs is because my first choice was f:t(cos(π(t+1))sin(π(t+1))), however that didn't match up with the picture. The picture goes clockwise from the south pole, this would go anticlockwise from the east pole.

Part 2

Define an equivalence relation on [1,1] by declaring 11, use part 1 above and applying the topological version of passing to the quotient to find a continuous bijection: (:[1,1]S1)

Solution

We wish to apply passing to the quotient. Notice:

  1. we get π:[1,1][1,1], π:x[x] automatically and it is continuous.
  2. we've already got a map, f, of the form (:[1,1]S1)

In order to use the theorem we must show:

  • "f is constant on the fibres of π", that is:
    • x,y[1,1][π(x)=π(y)f(x)=f(y)]
  • Proof:
    • Let x,y[1,1] be given
      • Suppose π(x)π(y), by the nature of implies we do not care about the RHS of the implication, true or false, the implication holds, so we're done
      • Suppose π(x)=π(y), we must show that this means f(x)=f(y)
        • It is easy to see that if x(1,1)R then π(x)=π(y)y=x
          • By the nature of f being a function (only associating an element of the domain with one thing in the codomain) and having y=x we must have: f(x)=f(y)
        • Suppose x{1,1}, it is easy to see that then π(x)=π(y)y{1,1}
          • But f(1)=f(1) so, whichever the case, f(x)=f(y)

We may now apply the theorem to yield:

  • a unique continuous map, ¯f:[1,1]/∼→S1 such that f=¯fπ

The question requires us to show this is a bijection, we must show that \newcommand{\fbar}{\bar{f} }\fbar is both injective and surjective:

  1. Surjective: \forall y\in \mathbb{S}^1\exists x\in \frac{[-1,1]}{\sim}[\fbar(x)=y]
    • There are two ways to do this:
      1. Note that (from passing to the quotient) that if f is surjective, then the resulting \fbar is surjective.
      2. Or the long way of showing the definition of \fbar being a surjection, \forall y\in\mathbb{S}^1\exists x\in\frac{[-1,1]}{\sim}[\fbar(x)=y]
        • Let y\in \mathbb{S}^1 be given.
          • Note that f is surjective, and f=\fbar\circ\pi, thus \exists p\in[-1,1] such that p=f^{-1}(y)=(\fbar\circ\pi)^{-1}(y)=\pi^{-1}(\fbar^{-1}(y)), thus \pi(p)=\fbar^{-1}(y)
          • Choose x\in[-1,1]/\sim to be \pi(p) where p\in[-1,1] exists by surjectivity of f and is such that f(p)=y
            • Now \fbar(\pi(p))=f(p) (by definition of \fbar) and f(p)=y, as required.
  2. Injective:
    • Let x,y\in\frac{[-1,1]}{\sim} be given. We wish to show that \fbar(x)=\fbar(y)\implies x=y
      • Suppose \fbar(x)\ne\fbar(y), then we're done, as by the nature of logical implication we do not care about the right hand side.
        • Note though, by the definition of \fbar being a function we cannot have x=y in this case! As a function must map each element of the domain to exactly one thing of the codomain. Anyway!
      • Suppose \fbar(x)=\fbar(y), we must show that in this case we have x=y.
        • By surjectivity of \pi:[-1,1]\rightarrow\frac{[-1,1]}{\sim} we see \exists a\in [-1,1]\big[\pi(a)=x\big] and \exists b\in [-1,1]\big[\pi(b)=y\big]
          • Notice now we have \fbar(x)=\fbar(\pi(a)) and that (from the passing to the quotient part of obtaining \fbar) we have f=\fbar\circ\pi, this means:
            • \fbar(x)=\fbar(\pi(a))=f(a), we also have \fbar(y)=\fbar(\pi(b))=f(b) from the same thoughts, but using y and b instead of x and a.
          • In particular: f(a)=f(b)
          • Now we have two cases, a\in(-1,1) and a\in\{-1,1\} , we shall deal with them separately.
            1. We have f(a)=f(b), suppose a\in(-1,1)
              • Recall that our very definition of f required it to be "almost injective", specifically that f\big\vert_{(-1,1)}:(-1,1)\rightarrow\mathbb{S}^1 was injective (and that it was only "not injective" on the endpoints)
              • As f is "injective in this range" we see that to have f(a)=f(b) means a=b (by injectiveness of f\big\vert_{(-1,1)} )
                • As a=b we see y=\pi(b)=\pi(a)=x and conclude y=x - as required.
            2. We have f(a)=f(b), and this time a\in\{-1,1\} instead
              • Again by definition of f, we recall f(-1)=f(1) - it maps the endpoints of [-1,1] to the same point in \mathbb{S}^1.
              • To have f(a)=f(b) clearly means that b\in\{-1,1\} (regardless of what value a\in\{-1,1\} takes)
                • But \pi(a)=[a]=\{-1,1\} and also \pi(b)=[b]=\{-1,1\}
                • So we see y=\pi(b)=\{-1,1\}=\pi(a)=x, explicitly: x=y, as required
          • We have shown that in either case x=y
    • Since x,y\in\frac{[-1,1]}{\sim} was arbitrary, we have shown this for all x,y. The very definition of \fbar being injective.

Thus \fbar is a bijection

Part 3

Show that [-1,1]/\sim is homeomorphic to \mathbb{S}^1

Solution

To apply the "compact-to-Hausdorff theorem" we require:

  1. A continuous bijection, which we have, namely \fbar:\frac{[-1,1]}{\sim}\rightarrow\mathbb{S}^1
  2. the domain space, \frac{[-1,1]}{\sim} , to be compact, and
  3. the codomain space, \mathbb{S}^1, to be Hausdorff

We know the image of a compact set is compact, and that closed intervals are compact in \mathbb{R} , thus [-1,1]/\sim=\pi([1-,1]) must be compact. We also know \mathbb{R}^2 is Hausdorff and every subspace of a Hausdorff space is Hausdorff, thus \mathbb{S}^1 is Hausdorff.

We apply the theorem:

Question 7

Let D^2 denote the closed unit disk in \mathbb{R}^2 and define an equivalence relation on D^2 by setting x_1\sim x_2 if \Vert x_1\Vert=\Vert x_2\Vert=1 ("collapsing the boundary to a single point"). Show that \frac{D^2}{\sim} is homeomorphic to \mathbb{S}^2 - the sphere.

  • Hint: first define a surjection (:D^2\rightarrow\mathbb{S}^2) mapping all of \partial D^2 to the north pole. This may be defined using a good picture or a formula.

Solution

The idea is to double the radius of D^2, then pop it out into a hemisphere, then pull the rim to a point
Picture showing the "expanding D^2", the embedding-in-\mathbb{R}^3 part, and the "popping out"

Definitions:

  • H denotes the hemisphere in my picture.
  • E:D^2\rightarrow H is the composition of maps in my diagram that take D^2, double its radius, then embed it in \mathbb{R}^3 then "pop it out" into a hemisphere. We take it as obvious that it is a homeomorphism
  • f':H\rightarrow\mathbb{S}^2, this is the map in the top picture. It takes the hemisphere and pulls the boundary/rim in (along the blue lines) to the north pole of the red sphere. f'(\partial H)=(0,0,1)\in\mathbb{R}^3, it should be clear that for all x\in H-\partial H that f'(x) is intended to be a point on the red sphere and that f'\big\vert_{H-\partial H} is injective. It is also taken as clear that f' is surjective
  • Note: Click the pictures for a larger version
  • \frac{D^2}{\sim} and D^2/\sim denote the quotient space, with this definition we get a canonical projection, \pi:D^2\rightarrow D^2/\sim given by \pi:x\mapsto [x] where [x] denotes the equivalence class of x
  • Lastly, we define f:D^2\rightarrow\mathbb{S}^2 to be the composition of E and f', that is: f:=f'\circ E, meaning f:x\mapsto f'(E(x))

The situation is shown diagramatically below:

  • \xymatrix{ D^2 \ar[d]_\pi \ar[r]^E \ar@/^1.5pc/[rr]^{f:=f'\circ E} & H \ar[r]^{f'} & \mathbb{S}^2 \\ \frac{D^2}{\sim} }

Outline of the solution:

  • We then want apply the passing to the quotient theorem to yield a commutative diagram: \xymatrix{ D^2 \ar[d]_\pi \ar[r]^E \ar@/^1.5pc/[rr]^{f} & H \ar[r]^{f'} & \mathbb{S}^2 \\ \frac{D^2}{\sim} \ar@{.>}[urr]_{\bar{f} } }
    • The commutative diagram part merely means that f=\bar{f}\circ\pi[Note 1]. We get f=\bar{f}\circ\pi as a result of the passing-to-the-quotient theorem.
    • We take this diagram as showing morphisms in the TOP category, meaning all arrows shown represent continuous maps. (Obviously...)
  • Lastly, we will show that \bar{f} is a homeomorphism using the compact-to-Hausdorff theorem
Solution body

First we must show the requirements for applying passing to the quotient are satisfied.

  • We know already the maps involved are continuous and that \pi is a quotient map. We only need to show:
    • f is constant on the fibres of \pi, which is equivalent to:
      • \forall x,y\in D^2[\pi(x)=\pi(y)\implies f(x)=f(y)]
  • Let us show this remaining condition:
    • Let x,y\in D^2 be given.
      • Suppose \pi(x)\ne\pi(y), then by the nature of logical implication the implication is true regardless of f(x) and f(y)'s equality. We're done in this case.
      • Suppose \pi(x)=\pi(y), we must show that in this case f(x)=y(y).
        • Suppose x\in D^2-\partial D^2 (meaning x\in D^2 but x\notin \partial D^2, ie - denotes relative complement)
          • In this case we must have x=y, as otherwise we'd not have \pi(x)=\pi(y) (for x\in D^2-\partial D^2 we have \pi(x)=[x]=\{x\}, that is that the equivalence classes are singletons. So if \pi(x)=\pi(y) we must have \pi(y)=[y]=\{x\}=[x]=\pi(x); so y can only be x)
          • If x=y then by the nature of f being a function we must have f(x)=f(y), we're done in this case
        • Suppose x\in \partial D^2 (the only case not covered) and \pi(x)=\pi(y), we must show f(x)=f(y)
          • Clearly if x\in\partial D^2 and \pi(x)=\pi(y) we must have y\in\partial D^2.
            • E(x) is mapped to the boundary/rim of H, as is E(y) and f'(\text{any point on the rim of }H)=(0,0,1)\in\mathbb{R}^3
            • Thus f'(E(x))=f'(E(y)), but f'(E(x)) is the very definition of f(x), so clearly:
              • f(x)=f(y) as required.

We may now apply the passing to the quotient theorem. This yields:

  • A continuous map, \bar{f}:D^2/\sim\rightarrow\mathbb{S}^2 where f=\bar{f}\circ\pi
\xymatrix{ D^2 \ar[d]_\pi \ar[r]^E \ar@/^1.5pc/[rr]^{f} & H \ar[r]^{f'} & \mathbb{S}^2 \\ \frac{D^2}{\sim} \ar@{.>}[urr]_{\bar{f} } }
Commutative diagram of situation
(all maps are continuous)
We now have the situation of the diagram on the right, restated from above for convenience.

In order to apply the compact-to-Hausdorff theorem and show \bar{f} is a homeomorphism we must show it is continuous and bijective. We already have continuity (as a result of the passing-to-the-quotient theorem), we must show it is bijective.

We must show \bar{f} is both surjective and injective:

  1. Surjectivity: We can get this from the definition of \bar{f} , recall on the passing to the quotient (function) page that:
    • if f is surjective then \bar{f} (or \tilde{f} as the induced function is on that page) is surjective also
      • I've already done it "the long way" once in this assignment, and I hope it is not frowned upon if I decline to do it again.
  2. Injectivity: This follows a similar to gist as to what we've done already to show we could apply "passing to the quotient" and for the other questions where we've had to show a factored map is injective. As before:
    • Let x,y\in\frac{D^2}{\sim} be given.
      • Suppose \bar{f}(x)\ne\bar{f}(y) - then by the nature of logical implication we do not care about the RHS and are done regardless of x and y's equality
        • Once again I note we must really have x\ne y as if x=y then by definition of \bar{f} being a function we must also have \bar{f}(x)=\bar{f}(y), anyway!
      • Suppose that \bar{f}(x)=\bar{f}(y), we must show that in this case x=y.
        • Note that by surjectivity of \pi that: \exists a\in D^2[\pi(a)=x] and \exists b\in D^2[\pi(b)=y], so \bar{f}(x)=\bar{f}(\pi(a)) and \bar{f}(y)=\bar{f}(\pi(b)), also, as \bar{f} was the result of factoring, we have f=\bar{f}\circ\pi, so we see \bar{f}(\pi(a))=f(a) and \bar{f}(\pi(b))=f(b), since \bar{f}(x)=\bar{f}(y) we get f(a)=f(b) and \bar{f}(\pi(a))=\bar{f}(\pi(b)) also.
          • We now have 2 cases, a\in D^2-\partial D^2 and a\in \partial D^2 respectively:
            1. Suppose a\in D^2-\partial D^2
              • As we have f(a)=f(b) we must have b=a, as if b\ne a then f(b)\ne f(a), because f\big\vert_{D^2-\partial D^2}:(D^2-\partial D^2)\rightarrow\mathbb{S}^2 is injective[Note 2] by construction
                • If b=a then y=\pi(b)=\pi(a)=x so y=x as required (this is easily recognised as x=y)
            2. Suppose a\in\partial D^2
              • Then to have f(a)=f(b) we must have b\in\partial D^2
                • This means a\sim b, and that means \pi(a)=\pi(b)
                  • But y=\pi(b) and x=\pi(a), so we arrive at: x=\pi(a)=\pi(b)=y, or x=y, as required.

We now know \bar{f} is a continuous bijection.

Noting that D^2 is closed and bounded we can apply the Heine–Borel theorem to show D^2 is compact. As \pi:D^2\rightarrow\frac{D^2}{\sim} is continuous (see quotient topology for information) we can use "the image of a compact set is compact" to conclude that \frac{D^2}{\sim} is compact.

A subspace of a Hausdorff space is a Hausdorff space, as \mathbb{S}^2 is a topological subspace of \mathbb{R}^3, \mathbb{S}^2 is Hausdorff.

We may now use the compact-to-Hausdorff theorem (as \bar{f} is a bijective continuous map between a compact space to a Hausdorff space) to show that \bar{f} is a homeomorphism

As we have found a homeomorphism between \frac{D^2}{\sim} and \mathbb{S}^2 we have shown they are homeomorphic, written:

  • \frac{D^2}{\sim}\cong\mathbb{S}^2.

Section C

Notes

  1. Jump up Technically a diagram is said to commute if all paths through it yield equal compositions, this means that we also require f=f'\circ E, which we already have by definition of f!
  2. Jump up Actually:
    • f\big\vert_{D^2-\partial D^2}:(D^2-\partial D^2)\rightarrow(\mathbb{S}^2-\{(0,0,1)\}) is bijective in fact!

References